About five years ago, prying on my father's library, I came across a book entitled Fez, City of Islam. The back cover informed that the author, Titus Burckhard, was the grandnephew of Jacob Burckhardt, the author of The civilization of the Renaissance in Italy.

My reading of Fez, City of Islam was sweet as only very few can be. Its prose was delicious; its content, of the highest culture. I felt as if, by virtue of a prodigy, I'd been induced to dream and walk myself the labyrinthine Fez. When I read it I was not at home, nor in my very country, not even in the present time, nor even was myself, but lived sequestered in a century and a place I never knew, and enjoyed in peace the life of a happier—though to me quite exotic—man.

Whether the book is truly as remarkable as I recall, it's difficult to say. It is often not the content what makes memorable a work of art, but the alchemy incurred upon its opposition to our peculiar state of conscience. I content myself to say that, in memory, the book is exquisite.

I recently acquired perchance another work of the author: Cosmology and modern science. It is a general critique of scientific knowledge as a whole, which emphasizes the invalidity of scientific models. The book contains an extensive section combating what then was modern psychology—namely, psychoanalysis—with particular stress over the work of Jung. The work, however, was a total disappointment. Only the most general comments were somewhat satisfactory or true; whenever a particular point was brought about, its justification was foul and arbitrary, and its claim backwards and medieval.

The foulness of the book is of a common category: dull fanaticism—or, as it is more commonly known, theology. This pointless discilpine has value only when excercised with a mix of creativity and rigour. That this is possible is proven by the examples of Scotus Eriugena, Origen of Alexandria, Pascal, Spinoza and Saint Agustine. That it is very rare is also proven by the lack of more examples, at least as far as my inquiries have gone. But even then, whatever value it has, is literary. (Origen's exegesis are simply exquisite to read, as are Augustine's Confessions and Pascal's Thoughts.) One may argue that literary value is enough to make these authors great, and this I do not object. But in what comes to philosophical matters, at least if philosophy is to have something to do with truth, however remotely, theology generally offers very little.

The above exceptions aside, all my readings of theology were at best bearable. Their arguments never followed a straight path, but like a serpent meandered in search of a conclusion in accordance with the Scriptures. Every conclusion was beforehand an assumption, and problematic questions were solved, with a slight of hand, by finding some convoluted sophistry that lead to the presupposed conclusion. I discovered the most arbitrary ways of thought, the most peculiar attempts at proof, the most extravagant arguments that human mind is capable of bearing. Metaphysics is often like this, but theology has the added component of a dogma, which is distasteful to anyone possessing at least a spark of sensitivity.

The work Cosmology and modern science was no exception to the sins I described above. For instance, at a certain point, the following chain of thought is exposed: Firstly, the notion of form, as understood by Greek philosophy, is defined. By form, the author correctly says, we understand the aggregation or association of the qualities of a thing or a being—its immutable essence. This is so that by form we understand a principle of individuation that, while in itself being nothing but an archetype, is to become manifest in connection to a matter or substance. (So far, Burckhardt only follows Dionysious the Aeropagite.) After providing and commenting on such definition, and arguing against some critiques of the notion, the author states:

From what was just said follows that a species is itself an immutable "form"; it could not evolve and transform into another species, although it may contain variations, which are diverse "projections" of a unique essential form of which they will never be separated—like the branches are never separated from the trunk.

The whole thesis of Darwin, he says, is based on a confusion (sic) between the concepts of species and variation. He soon after adds:

One may certainly find some fishes that use their fines to crawl in the sand, but in vain one would expect to find the least beginning of a joint, which is the only thing that would make the forming of a leg or an arm possible.

Yes, indeed: This is a refutation of Darwin based on the metaphysical concept of form, as understood by an Athenian convert that lived in the first century!

Only in metaphysics one can expect to find such bold attempts at arm-chair reasoning. None of it, needless to say, even hints at an interest for reality. First, a purely abstract concept is assumed to capture the true nature of things; then the desired conclusion is drawn from such assumption. It would be equally valid to assume the Pythagorean notion that all numbers are rational to prove that π is a rational number. (In fact, even this wouldn't be as flawed as Burckhardt's logic, in that the premise all numbers are rational is refutable, while the platonic assumptions of our author are almost a matter of taste.)

This, if any, is the method of theology: Take an arbitrary assumption, preferably based on ancient knowledge or primitive speculation, and use it only to derive a ridicule conclusion. The enterprise is to be judged depending on whether that conclusion, however obscene or stupid, agrees with whatever faith you happen to profess.

Burckhardt was also dissatisfied with Jungian psychoanalysis, which desacralizes religious experience and reduces religion to psychology. But every one of his arguments against the Jungian thesis boiled down to the assumption that the thesis is wrong; this is, to the assumption that the Abrahamic god is the true god, and the consequential proposition that religious experience is a supernatural phenomenon. At a certain point, Burckhardt claims that if the mind were an epiphenomenon of matter, it could not be termed to be intelligent—why this is so, nor why does it matter, he fails to say. He also states that, because the mind is capable of perceiving the essence of things (whatever that means), then there must be something essential and immutable to it—and that such eternal faculties of the mind are what Jung confuses with evolutionary endowments.

Burckhardt was a very sophisticated man in possession of an outstanding education. If anything, he's an example of the way in which fanaticism corrupts even potent intellects, rendering them sterile. Intelligence and education are in general not sufficient to acquire even the most elementary scientific intuition. Specially if one's central concern is agreeing with the barbaric doctrines of some ancient desert-wanderers.

It is hard to find anything of value in fanaticism. Yet, in general, it at least contains the appeal of Dionysiac fervour. Theology somehow obliterates this only, if not virtue, at least living characteristic. What remains is a sterile desert of narrow-mindedness and dogma.